Index
11. May Karol Smierc Judasza
May Karol Śmierć Judasza
May Karol W lochach Babilonu
Jeffries Sabrina Taniec zmysśÂ‚ów Stare panny Swanlea 04
03 Julie Kistler Na śÂ›lubie brata
Kroniki Brata Cadfaela 13 Róśźa w dani Peters Ellis
Carleen Sally Zostań na kolacj
Chris Manby Wojny w SPA
Heinlein, Robert A The Worlds of Robert A Heinlein
Graham Lynne Francuski kochanek
  • zanotowane.pl
  • doc.pisz.pl
  • pdf.pisz.pl
  • stardollblog.htw.pl

  • [ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]

    interpretation. We may refer to the position previously discussed as
    construction by objectification, the one to be examined here as
    construction by composition.
    THE MEANINGFULNESS OF ACTION ACCORDING
    TO WILHELM DILTHEY
    The doctrine that human action displays a distinct type of
     meaningfulness was pivotal to the writings of Wilhelm Dilthey and
    other seminal figures of nineteenth-century German thought. In its
    historical context this ontological doctrine was primarily advanced to
    buttress a specific methodological stance. Dilthey and kindred
    thinkers were concerned to demonstrate that the
    Geisteswissenschaften the sciences of man and culture should not
    be modelled on the natural sciences. In pressing this position, these
    authors put themselves in opposition to the prevailing tendency to see
    the sciences of man as susceptible of the same approach as that
    characteristic of the natural sciences; this methodological assumption
    had been imported into German thinking from abroad, through the
    writings of Auguste Comte and John Stuart Mill.
    Comte and Mill sought to institute a science of man capable of
    producing general laws of human action and explaining individual
    actions by subsuming them under such laws. By contrast, Dilthey
    insisted that the Geisteswissenschaften have a method uniquely their
    own, a claim encapsulated in his celebrated dictum,  We explain
    nature, but we understand mental life (Dilthey 1894:144). This is not
    to say that Dilthey rejected the possibility or usefulness of general
    truths and causal explanation in the  moral sciences , but merely that
    he insisted that these disciplines employ other and more specialised
    techniques as well.
    The distinction between two ways of grasping an object
    introduced by Dilthey in the dictum cited above is familiar from our
    everyday ways of thinking. We understand what people are about
    when, on a baking hot day, they go to the beach and plunge
    headlong into the sea; but we cannot understand, in the same sense,
    what propels a raindrop when it trickles down a rock, merges with
    104
    The Phenomenological Argument
    others to form a stream, ultimately to flow into the sea. In the first
    case, we appeal to wishes, desires and motives, whereas in the latter
    case, we can only cite the law of gravitation: water will tend to
    move towards the centre of gravity of the system of which it is a
    part, unless obstructed. Not since the Middle Ages have we
    attributed to water any desire to move to the centre of gravity, and
    even less to plunge into the sea.
    This familiar everyday contrast, however, is recast in highly
    theoretical terms in the context of Dilthey s philosophy, where it
    becomes clear how, in his view, it builds upon an ontological
    foundation. Underlying our everyday practices of explaining events
    and actions, and underlying, too, their sophisticated counterparts in
    the projected Science of Man, is the triad of Experience,
    Expression and Understanding.1  Experience is the ground and
    source of human action. It constitutes the subjective, mental life of
    man from which his actions flow as its manifestations. The critical
    thrust of the doctrine of experience was targeted at two widely
    divergent, contemporaneous conceptions of man which nonetheless
    share a strongly rationalist or intellectualist bias. One is the model
    of man that emerged in eighteenth century empiricist and
    enlightenment thought, and that lived on in the methodological
    writings of John Stuart Mill. This conception views human action
    as springing from two neatly separated mental sources, viz. beliefs
    and desires, while a third element, reason, serves to compute the
    proper way for these two to issue in action. The paradigm example
    of this kind of model is the economists homo economicus. The
    other conception finds expression in Hegel s view of history,
    which does not attribute reason primarily to individual human
    beings but instead ascribes it to a hidden agent of world history,
    Reason writ large. This quasiagent cunningly steers individual
    action towards the goal of world history.
    As against this, Dilthey s notions of  experience has a distinctive
    romantic tinge to it: experience is the undivided source of action in
    which thought, desire and will are indissolubly fused, not neatly
    segregated as the empiricist conception holds. Dilthey often refers to
    this holistic unity simply as  life . This conception is also intended to
    mark a contrast to Hegel s Reason,  life being a more empirical and
    contingent, less metaphysical, source of human history. History and
    society are formed through the aggregation of countless anonymous
    individual lives, not by the guiding power of a transcendent entity
    directing human action towards world-historical goals.
    105
    The Narrow Arguments
    Experience, in short, is man s subjectivity through which his
    ordinary, unreflectively lived existence is realised and mediated. It is
    in the nature of experience never to remain merely subjective,
    however, but to exteriorise itself in actions and in the permanent
    artefacts that actions leave behind: buildings, monuments, works of
    art, and written documents. In such artefacts, human experience is
    crystallised, perhaps to be extracted at a later point through the
    activities of the third member of Dilthey s triad of basic concepts,
    understanding.
    In characterising understanding, Dilthey uses such terms as
     reexperiencing ,  recreating , and  empathising . Understanding is
    seen as somehow replicating the state of  experience that the agent
    was in when he performed the act, produced the work of art or built
    the monument. This is not to say, however, that Dilthey considered
    understanding to be a simple, intuitive act. On the contrary, the
    interpretative enterprise will often expand into a general discursive
    process where the object of understanding, for instance, an
    individual human action, is situated in a larger context of
    comparable actions, either those performed by the agent in the
    course of a lifetime, or more broadly, those actions figuring in the
    context of an entire epoch or society. This is often apt when we
    seek to understand a historical figure as a  child of his times , as it
    is often put. Understanding proceeds through a tacking back and
    forth between the individual act and its wider setting, gradually
    reaching to deeper levels through so doing; this is the celebrated
    hermeneutical circle. Nonetheless, the unit operation in this entire
    process of interpretation remains the simple experiential state of
    empathy.
    Such, then, were the ideas that Dilthey bequeathed to his
    successors: in the first place, a strict division between the
    methodological procedures used in the two realms of natural
    science and the Geisteswissenschaften, the sciences of man.
    Secondly, this division is represented as reflecting an ontological
    difference: natural phenomena are ontologically monistic, whereas
    phenomena involving man have a composite nature. They have an
     outside , which may actually be made the object of naturalistic
    investigation, but also an  inside , consisting of that primordial
    stratum of human existence,  experience . For Dilthey and his
    followers, this doctrine was seen primarily as an argument in
    favour of a specific methodology, a move in the Methodenstreit
    between positivists and anti-positivists in German social science
    106
    The Phenomenological Argument
    around the turn of the century. But the doctrine in question can be
    put to immediate effect with respect to the themes that concern us
    here, viz., as an argument in support of a viable version of social [ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]
  • zanotowane.pl
  • doc.pisz.pl
  • pdf.pisz.pl
  • qualintaka.pev.pl
  • 
    Wszelkie Prawa Zastrzeżone! Lubię Cię. Bardzo. A jeszcze bardziej się cieszę, że mogę Cię lubić. Design by SZABLONY.maniak.pl.